Tuesday, July 17, 2007

Barnett on Libertarianism, the War and Ron Paul

Today's online FOX Wall Street OpinionJournal includes a column by Georgetown Law professor Randy E. Barnett entitled Libertarians and the War. He is especially keen to make the point that Ron Paul's opposition to the Iraq War is not the 'official' libertarian position and that one can be, as many libertarians were and some still are, supportive of the war without grave violation to what they hold to be the essence of libertarianism.

This is certainly true, though not entirely for the reasons Mr. Barnett articulates, and the key word is "entirely." There simply is no single set of libertarian principles shared by all who define their political views as such, so Barnett's unqualified claim that "libertarians believe in robust rights of private property, freedom of contract, and restitution to victims of crime ... that ... define true 'liberty'" is not, strictly speaking, true. Some do, some don't, and that is a point at least worth making as his point that Dr. Paul does not speak for all libertarians.

There is something structurally odd about that quoted assertion (the literal text of which I have edited but the sense of which remains intact) and it is his unqualified assertion of certain rights as definitional of (the oddly scare-quoted) liberty. The strong implication here is that libertarianism rests on some sort of natural rights theory, which indeed it does for many but does not for others, and that such view is the only (possible?) theoretical foundation of libertarianism. That is certainly wrong, and for several important reasons.

First, it is always important to distinguish moral claims of rights from legal rights. Legal rights exist, if at all, by operation of government including a legal system established to enforce such rights. I may or may not have a moral right to hold you to your promise to pay me for painting your house, but it is my legal right under the law of contracts that makes commerce possible. (Whether the mechanisms of legal rights enforcement must be governmental or can be privatized is a matter of dispute among libertarians but is irrelevant here.) So, too, whatever Lockean or other natural rights in property one might argue in philosophical debate, it is the law of property, essentially a creature of the state, that gives the contemporary concept of property most of its useful substance.

Natural rights theories have been out of fashion among academic philosophers for some time now. It is true that academic philosophers have a long and notorious history of changing their minds but being wrong both before and after, but that is not to deny that they have analyzed natural rights theories down to the subatomic level and found them wanting for good and serious reasons. My own view is that any theory of natural rights weak enough to be conceptually defensible is unlikely to be sufficiently robust to get most libertarianism where they want to go. That said, I also think that if any natural rights do "exist" (I trust my use of scare-quotes makes sense here), they include the moral right under most circumstances to be left the hell alone. (That is, I take individual autonomy to be presumptively legitimate and the moral burden on those who would violate it, but that does not quite equate to a theory of natural rights.)

In any case, while one can attempt to defend libertarianism in terms of rights and duties (to use the philosophical jargon, on deontological grounds), many prefer a purely consequentialist, usually utilitarian, approach. They argue, in effect, that libertarianism, by maximizing individual liberty, results in or at least affords the greatest good for the greatest number or at least the greatest opportunity for the greatest good or some such. Barnett inches toward that justification in the same paragraph, claiming that his rights defined concept of liberty:
... provide[s] the boundaries within which individuals may pursue happiness by making their own free choices while living in close proximity to each other. Within these boundaries, individuals can actualize their potential while minimizing their interference with the pursuit of happiness by others.

This formulation, interestingly enough, is a "virtue ethics" approach; that is, an ethical justification that goes to the goal of individual self-actualization or flourishing in the Aristotelian sense rather than the objective of collective good that tends to be the focus of most political theory.

It isn't so much that I disagree with what I think is Barnett's rather muddled one paragraph justification of libertarianism (it is, after all, only one paragraph and in an opinion column at that), as that it needs to be said that libertarianism as a living political movement is more about its generally shared conclusions than its specific theoretical justifications. That said, it is certainly true that Ron Paul's current fifteen minutes of fame could well misrepresent libertarianism in general and Barnett is correct to point that out. I might add that Paul's position on abortion, which I largely share, is even less widely held by libertarians.

Finally, I suspect Barnett is mistaken in his implied belief that most of the Americans who have taken note of Paul identify him as a libertarian. Whether they do or not, the presence of an elected official and major party presidential candidate voicing libertarian themes and receiving even modestly positive reactions among the public at large is surely of greater value than the loss of any prospective converts to libertarianism because of Paul's anti-war position. On that point he happens to be in the majority at the moment, a fact that augurs well for the prospects of liberty in post-Bush America.

1 comment:

Anonymous said...

I was most astounded by Barnett's list of reasons that allegedly justified the conquest of Iraq. They had little to do with self-defense, really. The legal reasons he provided struck me as naive rehashes of one-sided arguments that have nothing to do with liberty -- for instance, taking a position regarding "no fly" zones that I can't imagine any American would adopt were we being contained and bombarded, say, by China.

Is not the truth of the matter that the U.S. -- and the world with it -- had been at war with Iraq's Ba'athist regime since right after the Kuwaiti invasion, and that it in a sense never stopped. There had been no reasonable conclusion, only a series of rather witless demands and disastrous embargoes and bursts of firepower. Iraq was a conquered province in which the ruling power was made a quasi-subject. It was not a situation that could or should have continued.

But the debate begun by the Bush administration was in no sense honest. And Barnett's support for the administration's war shows the dangers of compromise on matters such as these. The Bush people lied through their teeth, and most of the world's leaders refused to speak the major truths of the situations, in support OR in opposition.

In such a situation, there was no way that Barnett's goal of establishing a friendly regime was likely, especially amongst Muslims of the Shia and Sunni varieties.

One is not entitled to come to sides on a third-party conflict even if one knows which side is "the good" WHEN there is almost no hope of making things better.

Americans, Bush-supporters, and Barnett err to think that we Americans can easily dictate terms of sovereignty to Muslims. To think so is to misunderstand Islam. (As well as nationalism.)

Bringing up Japan and Germany is, in a sense, rather witless, isn't it? Iraq and Iran are NOT Japan or Germany. Countries this different suggest that different lessons may apply.

I might have supported the conquest of Iraq had I believed the planners of said conquest were telling the truth (they were not, we know this for certain now; before the conqust I had only my intuition and reason to go by) and had they the sense to get out quickly after conquest. There were ways of dealing with Muslims that would have made the conquest halfway plausible. Not one of those ways (all depending on a certain humility from American leaders, something they are habitually out of practice in showing) was chosen.

Is Ron Paul thus right on the matter? He scored points by bringing up Reagan's hindight opinion on the Mid-East and its manageability. He also scored points by supporting the conquest of the Taliban, a feature that Barnett chose not to bring up. This shows Paul is capable of making crucial distinctions that emboldened imperialists like the Bush-Cheney junta have not been able to maintain.

Which proves to me that Paul is less of a fool of a libertarian than I had previously thought. Too often libertarian politicos speak from principle without experience, hope without reason.

It's strange to see a smart person like Randy Barnett lurch into naivety, isn't it? And see a man I thought rather naive (Ron Paul) scale new heights on the most important issue of the day.